Tuesday, August 19, 2008

Why Derrida? Why Grammatology?

I've been rereading Grammatology over this summer and it's left me with some need to revisit 1) why Derrida has interested me, and 2) why Of Grammatology has interested critics in the US.
If you'll permit the first autobiographical reflection, let me begin by saying I never really understood what he was saying until about a year ago, and I only did so because I just kept reading as much of him as I could. So the question really is why I continued to read him when I didn't really understand what he was getting at?
I was introduced to him in a class on theory--like many students, I think. I was initially very resistant to things that he was saying, being more Kantian and Hegelian in spirit, and more interested  generally in philosophy of mind. But what turned me on about him was spending a lot of time with a few essays of his--and writing papers on them. What was so great was that he was extremely rewarding if you read him closely and tried to piece together what he was saying. Some might call this his "play on words" or whatever, but what was really interesting to me was the high rationalism at work in the construction of his sentences: like any good novel, you can really get a lot by working through them. This made me less resistant.
As I took more and more classes in philosophy, which I was pursuing at the same time, I began to see that this sentence-level aspect of the way Derrida wrote was neat, but ultimately less interesting to me than the way he worked with the philosophical tradition. As I personally became more interested in phenomenology as I was pursuing philosophy of mind, I found he plugged himself quite thoroughly into that sphere. But this did not make me reduce him to this tradition--as some are too quick to do. I gathered that there was a particular intellectual field that was very diverse and yet very coherent that was orienting his discourse, of which phenomenology was a major part. And I began to piece this field together. In short, the tradition of French philosophy from Canguilhem on became an interest to me.
But at the same time, I just kept reading Derrida. And what was interesting to me then was his way of reconstructing other works: in short, I found that Derrida was actually an amazing teacher in his written work. He would have to reconstruct the entire logic of a discourse, and what this produced was actually a really neat way of introduction into a particular way of thinking about whatever he was talking about. Most might presume that the reconstruction would have to be skewed or distorted, but usually Derrida is also reconstructing how the field he is working in is thinking about the particular issues. Side comments and little aphoristic remarks are what allow you to grasp this. Indeed, they are unintelligible, but what was striking to me was not that they are unintelligible because they play with words or whatever: they are unintelligible in their content, because they presuppose an entire set of arguments and indeed a point of view in looking at whatever text you are considering. In short, I liked his patience--not because it produced rigor, but because it was symptomatic of that field in which he worked. A good example of what I mean is his discussion of Freud and the mystic writing pad in Writing and Difference. There he tackles Freud's 1895 Project for a Scientific Psychology, which many people in France were rediscovering at the time. He reconstructs the logic of this Project, and in doing so allows you to see what people are talking about then. But at the same time, he gives you a take on it--and all of this happens before he really begins to fiddle with what is going on. These little reconstructions and set ups--the way he poses the problems, were really neat to me, and what kept me going even though I didn't understand where the hell he was going with them.
Thus, a lot of emphasis upon the key words Derrida gives critical theory (trace, etc.) was completely lost for me, and mostly willingly--this was a healthy sort of ascesis that actually helped me not to use much of what Derrida said in my work on literature. It also kept me from immediately using him in my work in philosophy: my concern with Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty and others seemed to have its own impetus. And yet, as this reconstruction of mine makes clear, one can see that both these interests--in literature and philosophy--often take their cue from Derrida, or orient themselves around trying to figure out what he was about. At a certain time, then, it all started to pay off in the form of more and more interconnections, and I really got a sense of where he was coming from--in other words, the field was reconstructed. What was made clear, however, was that Derrida was more at home as a thinker within the tradition of philosophy than in critical theory and the study of literature--I found most people who talked about him there were really too far away from the study of literature at the same time as they were horrible at philosophy. However, his spirit was more within these other spheres, precisely because they addressed questions (gender, for example) that were escaping philosophy (although I know now that in certain spheres--like ethics--they weren't and aren't).
If I had to do it all over again, I think a quicker way of understanding him would be just to go to France and work in their philosophy departments. But I don't like the way they work as much as the Americans, as odd as we are, and so I think I would have lost a lot. Quicker wouldn't necessarily be better, I guess.
But all this brings me back to Grammatology--my second point. I read this first, I think, after some of the short essays that first introduced me to Derrida. And reading it then, sort of passively looking for those points of orientation I spoke about above rather than for the definitions of things like trace and differance, on the one hand, or the overall argument, on the other--reading it then and in this way was something that actually made the book much more coherent to me, I find.
Reading it now, the thing seems pretty crazy. Huge, sprawling, disconnected, extremely radical, the work is much less clear about the key concepts of differance and trace than Speech and Phenomena, and at the same time is so massive in its force and its demands upon thinking generally that it isn't clear where its argument most hits at other than the entire philosophical tradition--something that is done more economically, I think, in Dissemination and certain essays in Margins of Philosophy (e.g. "The Pit and the Pyramid," "Ousia and Grammê," or "The Ends of Man"--take your pick). So it isn't clear to me why people turned to it and still turn to it to understand Derrida.
And yet, I somewhat understand it if I focus on the analysis of Rousseau, which is quite simply just brilliant. However, this is so massive and, again, sprawling, that I don't know if it has the same effect now as it would when it first came out--that is, when there was a certain consolidated understanding of Rousseau as, well, merely contradictory (not focused upon and determined by something like a supplement). Better now to tell someone to pick up Speech and Phenomena, again if they want to begin to see what Derrida is about. In other words, Grammatology is all about extending to the utmost what is accomplished in the analysis of Husserl, because it actually grasps the hugeness of the consequences of that analysis in Speech and Phenomena.
What are these consequences? Simply put, that a phenomenology of text would be impossible. And, in fact, more than impossible: it would require, if one did not just back down in front of it, a total revolution of phenomenology, where the concern with essence upon which it is founded has to be completely evacuated. Phenomenology would have to proceed without phenomenology, then. Text becomes a privileged phenomenon, then, within the tradition, because it disrupts it completely, as well (and here is where Rousseau comes in) as anywhere there is a concern with essence.
In a way, though, you need to understand the basic thesis before you can grasp these consequences extended throughout Rousseau and (in the beginning of the book) Levi-Strauss. And--here is what I really think--the first part of the book does not totally introduce you to them as clearly as other parts of Derrida, notably Speech and Phenomena.
That said, it is clear that what really is great about this book is how you see the "method" of analysis take shape--and I think this is why it was and is so popular as a sort of introduction or primer. What is also remarkable is the repetitiveness of the analysis: like Dissemination, what we get is a focus upon the logic of the supplement at every moment it seems to come up in the discourse. And yet, unlike Dissemination, we get more of a setup that inserts this work of focusing within the current discourse: the long discussion of the economy of pity, etc. with Starobinski et. al. is very odd, actually, because it doesn't clearly do what it seems it wants to do. This is a double task: 1) reconstruct Rousseau's discourse and 2) reconstruct our way of reacting to this discourse as indicative of our current (that is, at the time of Grammatology) way of looking at what threatens to revolutionize our philosophical moment. If one focuses on the effort of reading to do this, one really sort of mistakes what Derrida is doing here--quite simply because it is too much setup and makes the real reading have to account for too much. In other words, this is too external to the task.
Where Derrida is really reading is when he is describing the supplement and showing how it always can be explained two ways. In other words, the whole effort of peeling back what Rousseau describes--which is the supplement--from what he declares--which is either that the supplement is bad or good in a particular case. Here the "method" is happening, and one sees how you have to go about it. You have to try and enter the protocols of the text, as Spivak often tells her students. This sort of vague phrase means really that you have to reconstruct a logic that the supplement, which functions as the center of this logic, its anchor, will have to disrupt. Getting a handle on this disruption means moving back and forth between logics, trying to make the structure of the disruption--differance--appear in how it leaves a trace in all those logics--or rather how all those logics become not logics but traces. In short, you do not just point out where differance is operative, where what Rousseau declares is different from what he describes. This is to say Rousseau thinks something "without thinking it." Rather, you show how the description is coextensive with the declaration--that is, you show that differance is coextensive with the articulation of the discourse itself. This is what Derrida means in the following:

It does not suffice to say that Rousseau thinks the supplement without thinking it, that he does not match his saying and his meaning, his descriptions and his declarations. One must still organize this separation and this contradiction.
-Of Grammatology, 245.

And this organization in fact exceeds what it organizes, as Derrida goes on to say. In the end, reading Grammatology, you really begin to see how this work of analysis functions--or at least what it would require. I personally think Dissemination ("Plato's Pharmacy") shows it more purely or at least more cleanly, but as it is, Grammatology remains a great example of this method or work--which is of course not a method and, as a working, an unworking.
But back to Rousseau: why this work is so amazing is not necessarily because it can account for things we that merely seem oddly contradictory in Rousseau ("I am the least vain of anyone," he says somewhere in the first book of the Confessions and remains for me the greatest, most hilarious example) as I might have suggested a bit earlier, but because this account proceeds in the way it does. Quite simply, it shows that Rousseau is a modern thinker of phusis, growth and generation. And at the same time it shows that this thought of growth is not possible for the moderns--a thought that in fact makes it possible that the ancients never really thought it either. Nature, that amazing force in Rousseau, is so conflicted that this becomes absolutely clear: however, its remains conflicted not because it is pure, but because it always has to articulate itself. In other words, because it is impossible, and impossible in such a way that it is the only thing that makes the discourse of Rousseau in its totality possible. Hegel, Marx, Freud, whoever--these thinkers might have very crucial parts of their discourse governed in this way by impossibility, but no one has it so totally and so crucially articulated it as Rousseau.
I could go on, but all I wanted to do was bring out both my reasons for reading Derrida and my reasons from shying away from various aspects of Grammatology as an introduction to Derrida--with the requisite highlighting of what is indeed important about it, which I think is not what we usually hear. We usually hear all this stuff about text and writing, but this is only the first part of the work (which I think many simply are content with reading, after which they put the book down). But all this is outlined in Speech and Phenomena and Writing and Difference. What is unique and important about Grammatology is that it works out the way that this problem of writing and text diffuses itself or allows discourses to be determined by it. Thus, it is appropriately wild and sprawling and odd--it has to exhaustively show discourse as trace. But this I think needs to be now seen as its virtue more than the simple thesis about grammatology as a positive science. If one wants this, one should look at a more pure, more clean analysis of Derrida's.
In other words, the sprawling, exhaustive aspect of the analysis here (the fact that it accounts for so much in Rousseau, not as much the aspect of the analysis that deals with inserting it into a current debate on Rousseau) has to be looked at as its odd core--its dispersion as its coherence, in a nutshell--because it is the most interesting working out of a way to talk about that impossibility: it is the work of analysis and reading when it is directed at what is impossible to analyze and read. In short, I think looking at it as less a finished work than a work in progress, a work of reading in progress, is necessary to appreciate it and indeed appreciate its genius. Looking for ideas like trace and differance needs to be done elsewhere. The analysis of Levi-Strauss should be looked at more in this manner too--and less as an attack or a condemnation of modern Rousseauism. But I might speak about this later--I've shied away from Levi-Strauss here so as to keep things simple and reconstruct my main thoughts about the book and my relationship to it.

9 comments:

Evan said...

> some of the short essays that first introduced me to > Derrida

Would you mind saying which exactly these were? I'd be interested to look at them. I took that semester-length Derrida course with Eduardo, but it focused more on the later work, and I never felt like I really got a handle on his earlier writings. (We read _Grammatology_ first, and it was kind of overwhelming.)

Anonymous said...

"Of Grammatology" is a terrible introduction to Derrida, and it's an odd historical accident that it got privileged (in the English-speaking world, at least) the way that it did. I think that if the early American readers of Derrida were more familiar with Husserl and less obsessed with Saussure, this would not have been the case.

In terms of which early work of Derrida would better serve as an entry, I'd second your recommendation of "Speech and Phenomena", or suggest "Violence and Metaphysics", all things being equal.

But, as always, the amount of insight one gets from any particular work of Derrida is directly proportional to one's intimacy with the text Derrida's work is parasitic upon.

Michael said...

Evan: it depends what you're familiar with. As Michael says below, it is best to see what text Derrida is being parasitic upon and then go from there. I wouldn't recommend "Violence and Metaphysics" to you, though, precisely for this reason: it requires a knowledge about Levinas and where he is at the time Derrida is writing. Generally, however, the texts in Margins of Philosophy are pretty good to start from. But even then they rely a bit more on phenomenology and I'd like if I was you. "Freud and the Scene of Writing" from Writing and Difference actually might be the best thing to begin with, since I'm guessing you probably know Freud. What might be best though, to get a flavor of things, would be a later essay done with very "early" concerns, "Envoi" in Psyche, Volume I. If you read Heidegger's "Age of the World Picture" before doing this (which is really interesting in and of itself) you will understand pretty well what is going on. So there are my recommendations:
1) "Freud and the Scene of Writing" which even if you don't really get at first will show you an interesting approach to Freud that will stick in your head I think and help you understand where Derrida is coming from,
2) Something from Margins: if you know Hegel, do "The Pit and the Pyramid,"--but even then that's the Hegel of the Encyclopedia, so it might not work. The Ends of Man is also good. I'd stay away from the performative stuff on speech acts ("Signature, Event, Context"), since people have gotten a little too into this and don't understand really how it fits into the rest of "vintage" Derrida's concerns (i.e. Judith Butler--who nevertheless is probably one of the best scholars of Derrida we have out there).
3) "Envoi" and "The Age of the World Picture" (in The Question Concerning Technology).

But other than that, maybe name a thinker you are pretty familiar with (other than Bourdieu) and I might be able to better help you out--I also have to think of whether "Differance" (in Margins and Speech and Phenomena) is good to read or not... that might also work, though it moves very very quick and a lot of people I think don't get it, rightly.

Michael: I think you put it right: knowing Husserl instead of Saussure would have been better. But it isn't so much an accident though that Saussure and Grammatology was our way of introduction--I hoped I hinted at this enough above. Generally I think that was an error in the teaching of Derrida, not in the reception of Derrida, as many people claim. Grammatology is huge in its ramifications--it really tries to hit at everywhere--and in clearer ways therefore perhaps than a real reading of Husserl... It might allow more points of entry than something else... maybe? The thing to do though is not call it an accident: this is a way to erase a lot of stuff that has happened and a lot of the thrust of Derrida's work, which was indeed very responsive to the concerns of his times. This is the way a lot of British philosophers I think are approaching him, and I think it remains too interested in a claim of philosophers to take over Derrida from literature and theory, who originally vied against philosophy when they took over Derrida. In short, its another power struggle of sorts to characterize it that way. One has to bring Derrida out of them when one considers him in America, at least. That's why I think it's better to see him within France, as conflicted as that itself is.

Steck said...

Right now I'm just starting to introduce myself to Derrida. I'm reading a short book called "How to read Derrida". My reactions have been mixed. Maybe because some of my questions remain unanswered. For example the book has covered his deconstruction of speech vs writing and other dualities. But I'm concerned with the duality between truth and falsehood. If these concepts were to be deconstructed what would become of truth?Would there be a plurality of truths?Would truth be shown to be a empty concept?A fiction based on shared cultural opinion?Right now I'm thinking Derrida would merely say that this shows that the concept of truth cannot be exist without falsehood to contrast with it, that all falsehood points toward truth and all truth points towards falsehood. But I could be wrong as i am not yet well versed in Derrida yet . I also wonder to what extent does Derrida's project undermine Heidegger?

Michael said...

That book is indeed not that great, actually--a better introduction is Jacques Derrida: Live Theory. Check that out: it has a very good stress on ethics and is actually very clear and (in my opinion) highly accurate.
But even better, see Derrida for yourself: read that essay in Psyche: Inventions of the Other recommended to Evan above--"Envois"--and you'll probably really get everything about Heidegger and how that works. Also, in volume II of Psyche read the "Geschlecht" series of essays.
On truth: the easy way to think about it is in Heideggerian terms. Think the essence of truth without essence. It isn't that there isn't truth, just that truth is only representation (in Heideggerian terms). But what is significant is that this precisely doesn't mean truth is something cultural--that is, only on the level of those sorts of representations. It is also more originary than being, or the essence of truth. Truth is more originary than the essence of truth at the same time as it is, according to the Heideggerian schema, the most derivative with respect to the essence of truth.
This is only a sketch. But I came across a good remark in Grammatology that might elucidate things:

All concepts determining a non-supplementarity (nature, animality, primitivism, childhood, madness, divinity, etc.) have evidently no truth value. They belong, moreover, with the idea of truth itself--to an epoch of supplementarity.
-p. 245

The word to focus on here is "evidently:" as usual in Derrida, this little word makes all the difference. What would it mean to say "all concepts that do not partake of a supplementary structure (a structure of writing, a structure of differance)--in other words, everything considered in its essence, considered as such--have evidently no truth value." It would mean precisely that if we say there is no truth value to anything, we could only say this precisely with some reference to truth--that is, with some sort of evidentiary claim (a claim to truth). In other words, it doesn't mean that truth is just communally held and relative: it means that truth is always determined locally--only locally, such that you can never actually be sure you are determining it. Any effort to say: the truth of this is x, or, x is true, would have to miss or misrecognize the truth. And precisely because there is not no truth: we have to miss truth precisely because truth remains elsewhere. In short, truth does not exist: it is elsewhere and otherwise than something that has being or partakes in being. This does not mean it is therefore nothing: it is this opposition of being and nothing that is exceeded by the consideration of truth this way. One can't say "there is x"--and not because "x is not," but because x can both be and not be as far as our perspective upon x is concerned. This maybe starts you on the way to that question--I can talk about it more and more clearly, but I have to run for now!

Anonymous said...

You're right, of course, about the notion of the "accident", and it is a serious topic. I'm sorry I don't have time to follow it up more thoroughly at the moment, but for now I will say only:

a) A roll of the dice will never abolish chance, and
b) cf. "Mes Chances/My Chances"

Sand said...

I'm almost a week late to this comment party, but nonetheless:
As Mike and I have discussed several times before, my favorite "start here" text for Derrida is still "Structure, Sign, and Play" ("Plato's Pharmacy" is a close second).

I say this as someone who is actually not very well plugged into phenomenology and the Hegelian tradition; "S,S,P" I think is much easier to understand if you're coming at Derrida as a thinker of structures and patterns rather than as a philosopher (definitely the case for me).

As for Grammatology, I don't think it's a coincidence that that's the book that Derrida is best known through in the States while at the same time being best known in and through the English department; Grammatology's *supposed* privileging of the text over a normative, status-quo standard of "history" or "reality" (obviously a misreading that is, unfortunately, deeply entrenched) went hand in glove with the agenda of certain participants in the culture wars of the '80s, many of whom were fighting their battles in and around the field of literary criticism. Like everything else among the caste of traditional intellectuals, it all boils down to politics...

Anonymous said...

I would agree that "Structure, Sign, and Play" is a good text to start with.
In addition, I think "Of Hospitality" as an excellent intro for non-philosophy people.
I also liked Gasche's "The Tain of the Mirror" as an "economical" introduction to the most important concepts of the Derridean thought.
Of course reading Derrida himself is an indispensable experience.

Michael said...

By no means are you late, Sand, to this comment-fest! You say:

I say this as someone who is actually not very well plugged into phenomenology and the Hegelian tradition; "S,S,P" I think is much easier to understand if you're coming at Derrida as a thinker of structures and patterns rather than as a philosopher (definitely the case for me).

I totally agree, but I do think that it is crucial someone not familiar with the phenomenological tradition approach things in your way and not in the way that SSP is usually approached: with the emphasis on the Saussure.
In other words, everything revolves around seeing "structures and patterns" everywhere, as you say--this is the only reason I myself like the phenomenological route and indeed this is the only way one should see the Saussure.
That means that, of course, the Saussure approach is just as advocated by me here in phenomenology: both are frameworks, as it were, for approaching what Derrida does. But the real crucial thing lies between them, in that ability to be interested in patterns and patterning, and then see what happens with them when they break down and build themselves up again.
This is what is lost, I think, when we just focus on where the signifiers and the signified are, and see how play produces itself out of them--which is, I think, how we approach that essay here at least in the US. And this has to do with something larger that I speak to you often about: structuralism never hit home in the US. To an extent, phenomenology did more--and that's why I'm so into recommending it as an approach. The familiarity with looking at stuctures, looking at the world in terms of structures, really was there in France at least: one could really see this in how popular Barthes was and Mythologies in particular. It's not really any harder or more noble a route than phenomenology, and vice versa--its just that you have to be able to see things in terms of it in order for what Derrida says in SSP to hit home. So either of these traditions is good for getting you into the way of thinking according to patterns, etc. Simply because this is not a common way of thinking--it needs to be entered into.
I personally find the phenomenology easier to see, myself--it is just more intuitive to me. But it could just as well be the Saussure. The problem is that the latter just was and i still think is not a common way of thinking about things here--even though, of course, we do it all the time but never notice it (I'm not trying to say Structuralism is really out there or anything--it's really common sense). This is the US's fault... and it also is a real fault of those who taught in that time here. How could they introduce Derrida and just skip over all of Structuralism? Well, the rest of your remark answers that: and that doesn't mean its dismissable either. Politics was important then in the classroom, as it is today--I don't mean to dismiss that either.
Sorry for the harried nature of this post: I'm trying to think it all out while not having a great connection to the internets... I hope I made myself clear. It seems that where you come from, the structuralist tradition--which doesn't mean so much knowing Saussure himself but actually being familiar with seeing the world in a sort of structuralist way (again, the world of Mythologies, of Barthes, with its ads and captions and choreographies, etc.)--this tradition is more cultivated--for better or worse--and this is what was not there in America and still isn't. So you have to do some extra work to read SSP, in my opinion, if you are doing it here: if you don't you end up with a lot of the mistaken ideas about Derrida that you indeed still see here as well.